Overcoming Deadlock: Scientific and Ethical Reasons to Embrace the Extended Mind Thesis
DOI:
https://doi.org/10.2298/FID1804489VKeywords:
extended cognition, intracranialism, embedded mind, ethics, theory selection, cognitive rehabilitationAbstract
The extended mind thesis maintains that while minds may be centrally
located in one’s brain-and-body, they are sometimes partly constituted
by tools in our environment. Critics argue that we have no reason to
move from the claim that cognition is embedded in the environment to
the stronger claim that cognition can be constituted by the environment.
I will argue that there are normative reasons, both scientific and ethical,
for preferring the extended account of the mind to the rival embedded
account.
References
Adams, F. and K. Aizawa. (2008), The Bounds of Cognition. Blackwell Publishing.
Blitz, M. J. (2010), “Freedom of Thoughts for the Extended Mind: Cognitive Enhancement and the Constitution”, Wisconsin Law Review 4: 1049–1117.
Bratman, M. E. (1987), Intentions, Plans, and Practical Reasons. Center for the Study of Language and Information Publications.
Clark, A., and D. Chalmers. (1998), “The Extended Mind.” Analysis 58(1): 7–19.
Clark, A. (2008), Supersizing the Mind: Embodiment, Action, and Cognitive Extension. New York: Oxford University Press.
Clark, A. (2009), “Response to Jerry Fodor’s Review ‘Where Is My Mind?’”, Review of Supersizing the Mind. London Review of Books: Letters 31(6).
Clark, A. (2010). “Coupling, constitution, and the cognitive kind: A reply to Adams and Aizawa”. In: R. Menary (ed.), The Extended Mind. Cambridge: MIT Press, pp. 81–100.
Drayson, Z., and A. Clark. (Forthcoming). “Augmentation, Agency, and the Spreading of the Mental State.” <https://sites.google.com/site/zdrayson/papers>
Drayson, Z. (2010). “Extended Cognition and the Metaphysics of Mind”, Cognitive Systems Research 11(4): 367–377.
Garner, J. B., and P. H. Campbell. (1987), “Technology for Persons with Severe Disabilities: Practical and Ethical Considerations”, The Journal of Special Education 21(3): 122–132.
Levy, N. (2007a), “Chapter Six: The ‘Self’ of Self-Control”, Neuroethics: Challenges for the 21st Century. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 197–221.
Levy, N. (2007b), “Rethinking Neuroethics in the Light of the Extended Mind Thesis.” American Journal of Bioethics 7(9): 3–11.
Levy, N. (2011), “Neuroethics and the Extended Mind”. In: J. Illes et al (eds.), Oxford Handbook of Neuroethics, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 285–294.
King, C. (2016), “Learning Disability and the Extended Mind” Essays in Philosophy 17(2): 38–68.
Kuhn, T. (1977), The Essential Tension. Selected Studies in Scientific Tradition and Change, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Rowlands, M. (2010), The New Science of the Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Rupert, R. D. (2004), “Challenges to the Hypothesis of Extended Cognition”, Journal of Philosophy 101(8): 389–428.
Shapiro, L. A. (2008), “Functionalism and the Boundaries of the Mind”, Cognitive Systems Research 9(5): 5–14.
Simon, H. (1969), The Sciences of the Artificial, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Sprevak, M. (2009), “Extended Cognition and Functionalism”, Journal of Philosophy 106: 503–527.
Vygotsky, L. (1930), Mind in Society: The Development of Higher Psychological Processes. M. Cole, V. John-Steiner, S. Scribner, and E. Souberman (eds), Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Downloads
Published
How to Cite
Issue
Section
License
Articles published in Philosophy and Society are open-access in accordance with the CC BY-NC-ND 4.0 License.